David Hume: Of Miracles, Part One |
Below is Part One of Enlightenment Philosopher David Hume's essay Of Miracles. If you would like to read an introduction to Hume's essay, click here: https://www.finding-meaning-in-life.com/p/introducing-david-humes-skeptical.html. For Part Two of Of Miracles, click here: https://www.finding-meaning-in-life.com/p/david-hume-of-miracles-part-two.html.
In editing the essay, only minor changes have been made to the text to modernize the spelling and punctuation.
Of Miracles, Part One
There
is, in Dr. Tillotson's[1]
writings, an argument against the real presence, which is as
concise, and elegant, and strong as any argument can possibly be supposed
against a doctrine, so little worthy of a serious refutation. It is
acknowledged on all hands, says that learned prelate, that the authority,
either of the scripture or of tradition, is founded merely in the testimony of
the apostles, who were eye-witnesses to those miracles of our Savior, by which
he proved his divine mission. Our evidence, then, for the truth of the Christian religion
is less than the evidence for the truth of our senses; because, even in the
first authors of our religion, it was no greater; and it is evident it must
diminish in passing from them to their disciples; nor can anyone rest such confidence
in their testimony, as in the immediate object of his senses. But a weaker
evidence can never destroy a stronger; and therefore, were the doctrine of the
real presence ever so clearly revealed in scripture, it were directly contrary
to the rules of just reasoning to give our assent to it. It contradicts sense,
though both the scripture and tradition, on which it is supposed to be built,
carry not such evidence with them as sense; when they are considered merely as
external evidences, and are not brought home to every one's breast, by the
immediate operation of the Holy Spirit.
Nothing
is so convenient as a decisive argument of this kind, which must at least silence the
most arrogant bigotry and superstition, and free us from their impertinent
solicitations. I flatter myself, that I have discovered an argument of a like
nature, which, if just, will, with the wise and learned, be an everlasting
check to all kinds of superstitious delusion, and consequently, will be useful
as long as the world endures. For so long, I presume, will the accounts of
miracles and prodigies be found in all history, sacred and profane.
Though
experience be our only guide in reasoning concerning matters of fact; it must
be acknowledged, that this guide is not altogether infallible, but in some
cases is apt to lead us into errors. One, who in our climate, should expect
better weather in any week of June than in one of December, would reason
justly, and conformably to experience; but it is certain, that he may happen,
in the event, to find himself mistaken. However, we may observe, that, in such
a case, he would have no cause to complain of experience; because it commonly
informs us beforehand of the uncertainty, by that contrariety of events, which
we may learn from a diligent observation. All effects follow not with like
certainty from their supposed causes. Some events are found, in all countries
and all ages, to have been constantly conjoined together: Others are found to
have been more variable, and sometimes to disappoint our expectations; so that,
in our reasonings concerning matter of fact, there are all imaginable degrees
of assurance, from the highest certainty to the lowest species of moral
evidence.
A
wise man, therefore, proportions his belief to the evidence. In such conclusions
as are founded on an infallible experience, he expects the event with the last
degree of assurance and regards his past experience as a full proof of
the future existence of that event. In other cases, he proceeds with more
caution: He weighs the opposite experiments: He considers which side is
supported by the greater number of experiments: to that side he inclines, with
doubt and hesitation; and when at last he fixes his judgement, the evidence
exceeds not what we properly call probability. All probability,
then, supposes an opposition of experiments and observations, where the one
side is found to overbalance the other, and to produce a degree of evidence,
proportioned to the superiority. A hundred instances or experiments on one
side, and fifty on another, afford a doubtful expectation of any event; though
a hundred uniform experiments, with only one that is contradictory, reasonably
beget a pretty strong degree of assurance. In all cases, we must balance the
opposite experiments, where they are opposite, and deduct the smaller number
from the greater, in order to know the exact force of the superior evidence.
To
apply these principles to a particular instance; we may observe, that there is
no species of reasoning more common, more useful, and even necessary to human
life, than that which is derived from the testimony of men, and the reports of eyewitnesses
and spectators. This species of reasoning, perhaps, one may deny to be founded
on the relation of cause and effect. I shall not dispute about a word. It will
be sufficient to observe that our assurance in any argument of this kind is
derived from no other principle than our observation of the veracity of human
testimony, and of the usual conformity of facts to the reports of witnesses. It
being a general maxim, that no objects have any discoverable connection
together, and that all the inferences, which we can draw from one to another,
are founded merely on our experience of their constant and regular conjunction;
it is evident, that we ought not to make an exception to this maxim in favor of
human testimony, whose connection with any event seems, in itself, as little
necessary as any other. Were not the memory tenacious to a certain degree, had
not men commonly an inclination to truth and a principle of probity; were they
not sensible to shame, when detected in a falsehood: Were not these, I say,
discovered by experience to be qualities, inherent in human nature, we should
never repose the least confidence in human testimony. A man delirious, or noted
for falsehood and villainy, has no manner of authority with us.
And
as the evidence, derived from witnesses and human testimony, is founded on past
experience, so it varies with the experience, and is regarded either as a proof or
a probability, according as the conjunction between any particular kind
of report and any kind of object has been found to be constant or variable.
There are a number of circumstances to be taken into consideration in all
judgements of this kind; and the ultimate standard, by which we determine all
disputes, that may arise concerning them, is always derived from experience and
observation. Where this experience is not entirely uniform on any side, it is
attended with an unavoidable contrariety in our judgements, and with the same
opposition and mutual destruction of argument as in every other kind of
evidence. We frequently hesitate concerning the reports of others. We balance
the opposite circumstances, which cause any doubt or uncertainty; and when we
discover a superiority on any side, we incline to it; but still with a
diminution of assurance, in proportion to the force of its antagonist.
This
contrariety of evidence, in the present case, may be derived from several
different causes; from the opposition of contrary testimony; from the character
or number of the witnesses; from the manner of their delivering their
testimony; or from the union of all these circumstances. We entertain a
suspicion concerning any matter of fact, when the witnesses contradict each
other; when they are but few, or of a doubtful character; when they have an
interest in what they affirm; when they deliver their testimony with
hesitation, or on the contrary, with too violent asseverations. There are many
other particulars of the same kind, which may diminish or destroy the force of
any argument, derived from human testimony.
Suppose,
for instance, that the fact, which the testimony endeavors to establish,
partakes of the extraordinary and the marvelous; in that case, the evidence,
resulting from the testimony, admits of a diminution, greater or less, in
proportion as the fact is more or less unusual. The reason why we place any
credit in witnesses and historians, is not derived from any connection,
which we perceive a priori, between testimony and reality, but
because we are accustomed to find a conformity between them. But when the fact
attested is such a one as has seldom fallen under our observation, here is a
contest of two opposite experiences; of which the one destroys the other, as
far as its force goes, and the superior can only operate on the mind by the
force, which remains. The very same principle of experience, which gives us a
certain degree of assurance in the testimony of witnesses, gives us also, in
this case, another degree of assurance against the fact, which they endeavor to
establish; from which contradiction there necessarily arises a counterpoise,
and mutual destruction of belief and authority.
I
should not believe such a story were it told me by Cato,
was a proverbial saying in Rome, even during the lifetime of that philosophical
patriot. The incredibility of a fact, it was
allowed, might invalidate so great an authority.
The
Indian prince, who refused to believe the first relations concerning the
effects of frost, reasoned justly; and it naturally required very strong
testimony to engage his assent to facts, that arose from a state of nature,
with which he was unacquainted, and which bore so little analogy to those
events, of which he had had constant and uniform experience. Though they were
not contrary to his experience, they were not conformable to it.
But
in order to increase the probability against the testimony of witnesses, let us
suppose, that the fact, which they affirm, instead of being only marvelous, is
really miraculous; and suppose also, that the testimony considered apart and in
itself, amounts to an entire proof; in that case, there is proof against proof,
of which the strongest must prevail, but still with a diminution of its force,
in proportion to that of its antagonist.
A
miracle is a violation of the laws of nature; and as a firm and unalterable
experience has established these laws, the proof against a miracle, from the
very nature of the fact, is as entire as any argument from experience can possibly
be imagined. Why is it more than probable, that all men must die; that lead
cannot, of itself, remain suspended in the air; that fire consumes wood, and is
extinguished by water; unless it be, that these events are found agreeable to
the laws of nature, and there is required a violation of these laws, or in
other words, a miracle to prevent them? Nothing is esteemed a miracle, if it
ever happens in the common course of nature. It is no miracle that a man,
seemingly in good health, should die on a sudden: because such a kind of death,
though more unusual than any other, has yet been frequently observed to happen.
But it is a miracle, that a dead man should come to life; because that has
never been observed in any age or country. There must, therefore, be a uniform
experience against every miraculous event, otherwise the event would not merit
that appellation. And as a uniform experience amounts to a proof, there is here
a direct and full proof, from the nature of the fact, against the
existence of any miracle; nor can such a proof be destroyed, or the miracle
rendered credible, but by an opposite proof, which is superior.
The
plain consequence is (and it is a general maxim worthy of our attention), 'That
no testimony is sufficient to establish a miracle, unless the testimony be of
such a kind, that its falsehood would be more miraculous, than the fact, which
it endeavors to establish; and even in that case there is a mutual destruction
of arguments, and the superior only gives us an assurance suitable to that
degree of force, which remains, after deducting the inferior.' When anyone
tells me, that he saw a dead man restored to life, I immediately consider with
myself, whether it be more probable, that this person should either deceive or
be deceived, or that the fact, which he relates, should really have happened. I
weigh the one miracle against the other; and according to the superiority,
which I discover, I pronounce my decision, and always reject the greater
miracle. If the falsehood of his testimony would be more miraculous, than the
event which he relates; then, and not till then, can he pretend to command my
belief or opinion.
[1]
Dr. Tillotson wrote The Rule of Faith, in which he attacked the Roman
Catholic doctrine of transubstantiation, i.e., the belief that during
celebration of the Eucharist, the bread and wine actually become the body and
blood of Christ.
Of Miracles Part Two by David Hume
Click here to read Of Miracles Part Two by David Hume next: https://www.finding-meaning-in-life.com/p/david-hume-of-miracles-part-two.html or you can return to the Finding Meaning in Life homepage here: https://www.finding-meaning-in-life.com/
No comments:
Post a Comment
Thank you for taking the time to read and comment on this blog!
Best regards,
Daniel D