David Hume: Of Miracles, Part Two |
Below is Part Two of David Hume's essay Of Miracles. In editing the text, I made only minor changes to modernize the spelling and punctuation. To read Part One of this essay, click here: https://www.finding-meaning-in-life.com/p/david-hume-of-miracles-part-one.html. For an introduction to David Hume, his philosophy of skeptical empiricism, and an overview of Of Miracles, click here: https://www.finding-meaning-in-life.com/p/introducing-david-humes-skeptical.html.
Of Miracles by David Hume, Part Two
In
the foregoing reasoning we have supposed, that the testimony, upon which a
miracle is founded, may possibly amount to an entire proof, and that the
falsehood of that testimony would be a real prodigy: But it is easy to shew,
that we have been a great deal too liberal in our concession, and that there
never was a miraculous event established on so full an evidence.
For first,
there is not to be found, in all history, any miracle attested by a sufficient
number of men, of such unquestioned good-sense, education, and learning, as to
secure us against all delusion in themselves; of such undoubted integrity, as
to place them beyond all suspicion of any design to deceive others; of such
credit and reputation in the eyes of mankind, as to have a great deal to lose
in case of their being detected in any falsehood; and at the same time,
attesting facts performed in such a public manner and in so celebrated a part
of the world, as to render the detection unavoidable: All which circumstances
are requisite to give us a full assurance in the testimony of men.
Secondly.
We may observe in human nature a principle which, if strictly examined, will be
found to diminish extremely the assurance, which we might, from human
testimony, have, in any kind of prodigy. The maxim, by which we commonly
conduct ourselves in our reasonings, is, that the objects, of which we have no
experience, resembles those, of which we have; that what we have found to be
most usual is always most probable; and that where there is an opposition of
arguments, we ought to give the preference to such as are founded on the
greatest number of past observations. But though, in proceeding by this rule,
we readily reject any fact which is unusual and incredible in an ordinary
degree; yet in advancing farther, the mind observes not always the same rule;
but when anything is affirmed utterly absurd and miraculous, it rather the more
readily admits of such a fact, upon account of that very circumstance, which
ought to destroy all its authority. The passion of surprise and wonder,
arising from miracles, being an agreeable emotion, gives a sensible tendency
towards the belief of those events, from which it is derived. And this goes so
far, that even those who cannot enjoy this pleasure immediately, nor can
believe those miraculous events, of which they are informed, yet love to
partake of the satisfaction at second-hand or by rebound, and place a pride and
delight in exciting the admiration of others.
With
what greediness are the miraculous accounts of travelers received, their
descriptions of sea and land monsters, their relations of wonderful adventures,
strange men, and uncouth manners? But if the spirit of religion join itself to
the love of wonder, there is an end of common sense; and human testimony, in
these circumstances, loses all pretensions to authority. A religionist may be
an enthusiast, and imagine he sees what has no reality: he may know his
narrative to be false, and yet persevere in it, with the best intentions in the
world, for the sake of promoting so holy a cause: or even where this delusion
has not place, vanity, excited by so strong a temptation, operates on him more
powerfully than on the rest of mankind in any other circumstances; and
self-interest with equal force. His auditors may not have, and commonly have
not, sufficient judgement to canvass his evidence: what judgement they have,
they renounce by principle, in these sublime and mysterious subjects: or if
they were ever so willing to employ it, passion and a heated imagination
disturb the regularity of its operations. Their credulity increases his
impudence: and his impudence overpowers their credulity.
Eloquence,
when at its highest pitch, leaves little room for reason or reflection; but
addressing itself entirely to the fancy or the affections, captivates the
willing hearers, and subdues their understanding. Happily, this pitch it seldom
attains. But what a Tully or a Demosthenes could scarcely effect over a Roman
or Athenian audience, every Capuchin, every itinerant or stationary
teacher can perform over the generality of mankind, and in a higher degree, by
touching such gross and vulgar passions.
The
many instances of forged miracles, and prophecies, and supernatural events,
which, in all ages, have either been detected by contrary evidence, or which
detect themselves by their absurdity, prove sufficiently the strong propensity
of mankind to the extraordinary and the marvelous, and ought reasonably to
beget a suspicion against all relations of this kind. This is our natural way
of thinking, even with regard to the most common and most credible events. For
instance: There is no kind of report which rises so easily, and spreads so
quickly, especially in country places and provincial towns, as those concerning
marriages; insomuch that two young persons of equal condition never see each
other twice, but the whole neighborhood immediately join them together. The
pleasure of telling a piece of news so interesting, of propagating it, and of
being the first reporters of it, spreads the intelligence. And this is so well
known, that no man of sense gives attention to these reports, till he find them
confirmed by some greater evidence. Do not the same passions, and others still
stronger, incline the generality of mankind to believe and report, with the
greatest vehemence and assurance, all religious miracles?
Thirdly.
It forms a strong presumption against all supernatural and miraculous
relations, that they are observed chiefly to abound among ignorant and
barbarous nations; or if a civilized people has ever given admission to any of
them, that people will be found to have received them from ignorant and
barbarous ancestors, who transmitted them with that inviolable sanction and
authority, which always attend received opinions. When we peruse the first
histories of all nations, we are apt to imagine ourselves transported into some
new world; where the whole frame of nature is disjointed, and every element
performs its operations in a different manner, from what it does at present.
Battles, revolutions, pestilence, famine and death, are never the effect of
those natural causes, which we experience. Prodigies, omens, oracles,
judgements, quite obscure the few natural events, that are intermingled with
them. But as the former grow thinner every page, in proportion as we advance
nearer the enlightened ages, we soon learn, that there is nothing mysterious or
supernatural in the case, but that all proceeds from the usual propensity of
mankind towards the marvelous, and that, though this inclination may at
intervals receive a check from sense and learning, it can never be thoroughly
extirpated from human nature.
It
is strange, a judicious reader is apt to say, upon the
perusal of these wonderful historians, that such prodigious events
never happen in our days. But it is nothing strange, I hope, that men
should lie in all ages. You must surely have seen instances enough of that
frailty. You have yourself heard many such marvelous relations started, which,
being treated with scorn by all the wise and judicious, have at last been
abandoned even by the vulgar. Be assured, that those renowned lies, which have
spread and flourished to such a monstrous height, arose from like beginnings;
but being sown in a more proper soil, shot up at last into prodigies almost
equal to those which they relate.
It
was a wise policy in that false prophet, Alexander, who though now forgotten,
was once so famous, to lay the first scene of his impostures in Paphlagonia,
where, as Lucian tells us, the people were extremely ignorant and stupid, and
ready to swallow even the grossest delusion. People at a distance, who are weak
enough to think the matter at all worth enquiry, have no opportunity of
receiving better information. The stories come magnified to them by a hundred
circumstances. Fools are industrious in propagating the imposture; while the
wise and learned are contented, in general, to deride its absurdity, without
informing themselves of the particular facts, by which it may be distinctly
refuted. And thus the impostor above mentioned was enabled to proceed, from his
ignorant Paphlagonians, to the enlisting of votaries, even among the Grecian
philosophers, and men of the most eminent rank and distinction in Rome: nay,
could engage the attention of that sage emperor Marcus Aurelius; so far as to
make him trust the success of a military expedition to his delusive prophecies.
The
advantages are so great, of starting an imposture among an ignorant people,
that, even though the delusion should be too gross to impose on the generality
of them (which, though seldom, is sometimes the case) it has a much
better chance for succeeding in remote countries, than if the first scene had
been laid in a city renowned for arts and knowledge. The most ignorant and
barbarous of these barbarians carry the report abroad. None of their countrymen
have a large correspondence, or sufficient credit and authority to contradict
and beat down the delusion. Men's inclination to the marvelous has full
opportunity to display itself. And thus, a story, which is universally exploded
in the place where it was first started, shall pass for certain at a thousand
miles distance. But had Alexander fixed his residence at Athens, the
philosophers of that renowned mart of learning had immediately spread,
throughout the whole Roman empire, their sense of the matter; which, being
supported by so great authority, and displayed by all the force of reason and
eloquence, had entirely opened the eyes of mankind. It is true; Lucian, passing
by chance through Paphlagonia, had an opportunity of performing this good
office. But, though much to be wished, it does not always happen, that every
Alexander meets with a Lucian, ready to expose and detect his impostures.
I
may add as a fourth reason, which diminishes the authority of
prodigies, that there is no testimony for any, even those which have not been
expressly detected, that is not opposed by an infinite number of witnesses; so
that not only the miracle destroys the credit of testimony, but the testimony
destroys itself. To make this the better understood, let us consider, that, in
matters of religion, whatever is different is contrary; and that it is
impossible the religions of ancient Rome, of Turkey, of Siam, and of China
should, all of them, be established on any solid foundation. Every miracle,
therefore, pretended to have been wrought in any of these religions (and all of
them abound in miracles), as its direct scope is to establish the particular
system to which it is attributed; so has it the same force, though more
indirectly, to overthrow every other system. In destroying a rival system, it
likewise destroys the credit of those miracles, on which that system was
established; so that all the prodigies of different religions are to be
regarded as contrary facts, and the evidences of these prodigies, whether weak
or strong, as opposite to each other. According to this method of reasoning,
when we believe any miracle of Mahomet or his successors, we have for our
warrant the testimony of a few barbarous Arabians: And on the other hand, we
are to regard the authority of Titus Livius, Plutarch, Tacitus, and, in short,
of all the authors and witnesses, Grecian, Chinese, and Roman Catholic, who
have related any miracle in their particular religion; I say, we are to regard
their testimony in the same light as if they had mentioned that Mahometan
miracle, and had in express terms contradicted it, with the same certainty as
they have for the miracle they relate. This argument may appear overly subtle
and refined; but is not in reality different from the reasoning of a judge, who
supposes, that the credit of two witnesses, maintaining a crime against any
one, is destroyed by the testimony of two others, who affirm him to have been
two hundred leagues distant, at the same instant when the crime is said to have
been committed.
One
of the best attested miracles in all profane history, is that which Tacitus
reports of Vespasian, who cured a blind man in Alexandria, by means of his
spittle, and a lame man by the mere touch of his foot; in obedience to a vision
of the god Serapis, who had enjoined them to have recourse to the Emperor, for
these miraculous cures. The story may be seen in that fine historian; where every circumstance seems to add weight to the testimony
and might be displayed at large with all the force of argument and eloquence,
if any one were now concerned to enforce the evidence of that exploded and
idolatrous superstition. The gravity, solidity, age, and probity of so great an
emperor, who, through the whole course of his life, conversed in a familiar
manner with his friends and courtiers, and never affected those extraordinary
airs of divinity assumed by Alexander and Demetrius. The historian, a contemporary
writer, noted for candor and veracity, and withal, the greatest and most
penetrating genius, perhaps, of all antiquity; and so free from any tendency to
credulity, that he even lies under the contrary imputation, of atheism and
profaneness: The persons, from whose authority he related the miracle, of
established character for judgement and veracity, as we may well presume;
eye-witnesses of the fact, and confirming their testimony, after the Flavian
family was despoiled of the empire, and could no longer give any reward, as the
price of a lie. Utrumque, qui interfuere, nunc quoque memorant,
postquam nullum mendacio pretium. To which if we add the public nature of
the facts, as related, it will appear, that no evidence can well be supposed
stronger for so gross and so palpable a falsehood.
There
is also a memorable story related by Cardinal de Retz, which may well deserve
our consideration. When that intriguing politician fled into Spain, to avoid
the persecution of his enemies, he passed through Saragossa, the capital of
Arragon, where he was shewn, in the cathedral, a man, who had served seven
years as a door-keeper, and was well known to everybody in town, that had ever
paid his devotions at that church. He had been seen, for so long a time,
wanting a leg; but recovered that limb by the rubbing of holy oil upon the
stump; and the cardinal assures us that he saw him with two legs. This miracle
was vouched by all the canons of the church; and the whole company in town were
appealed to for a confirmation of the fact; whom the cardinal found, by their
zealous devotion, to be thorough believers of the miracle. Here the relater was
also cotemporary to the supposed prodigy, of an incredulous and libertine
character, as well as of great genius; the miracle of so singular a
nature as could scarcely admit of a counterfeit, and the witnesses very
numerous, and all of them, in a manner, spectators of the fact, to which they
gave their testimony. And what adds mightily to the force of the evidence, and
may double our surprise on this occasion, is, that the cardinal himself, who
relates the story, seems not to give any credit to it, and consequently cannot
be suspected of any concurrence in the holy fraud. He considered justly, that
it was not requisite, in order to reject a fact of this nature, to be able
accurately to disprove the testimony, and to trace its falsehood, through all
the circumstances of knavery and credulity which produced it. He knew, that, as
this was commonly altogether impossible at any small distance of time and
place; so was it extremely difficult, even where one was immediately present,
by reason of the bigotry, ignorance, cunning, and roguery of a great part of
mankind. He therefore concluded, like a just reasoner, that such an evidence
carried falsehood upon the very face of it, and that a miracle, supported by
any human testimony, was more properly a subject of derision than of argument.
There
surely never was a greater number of miracles ascribed to one person, than
those, which were lately said to have been wrought in France upon the tomb of
Abbe Paris, the famous Jansenist, with whose sanctity the people were so long
deluded. The curing of the sick, giving hearing to the deaf, and sight to the
blind, were everywhere talked of as the usual effects of that holy sepulcher.
But what is more extraordinary; many of the miracles were immediately proved
upon the spot, before judges of unquestioned integrity, attested by witnesses
of credit and distinction, in a learned age, and on the most eminent theatre
that is now in the world. Nor is this all: a relation of them was published and
dispersed everywhere; nor were the Jesuits, though a learned body,
supported by the civil magistrate, and determined enemies to those opinions, in
whose favor the miracles were said to have been wrought, ever able distinctly
to refute or detect them. Where shall we find such a
number of circumstances, agreeing to the corroboration of one fact? And what
have we to oppose to such a cloud of witnesses, but the absolute impossibility
or miraculous nature of the events, which they relate? And this surely, in the
eyes of all reasonable people, will alone be regarded as a sufficient
refutation.
Is
the consequence just, because some human testimony has the utmost force and
authority in some cases, when it relates the battle of Philippi or Pharsalia
for instance; that therefore all kinds of testimony must, in all cases, have
equal force and authority? Suppose that the Caesarean and Pompeian factions
had, each of them, claimed the victory in these battles, and that the
historians of each party had uniformly ascribed the advantage to their own
side; how could mankind, at this distance, have been able to determine between
them? The contrariety is equally strong between the miracles related by
Herodotus or Plutarch, and those delivered by Mariana, Bede, or any monkish
historian.
The
wise lend a very academic faith to every report which favors the passion of the
reporter; whether it magnifies his country, his family, or himself, or in any
other way strikes in with his natural inclinations and propensities. But what
greater temptation than to appear a missionary, a prophet, an ambassador from
heaven? Who would not encounter many dangers and difficulties, in order to
attain so sublime a character? Or if, by the help of vanity and a heated
imagination, a man has first made a convert of himself, and entered seriously
into the delusion; whoever scruples to make use of pious frauds, in support of
so holy and meritorious a cause?
The
smallest spark may here kindle into the greatest flame; because the materials
are always prepared for it. The avidum genus auricularum, the gazing populace, receive greedily, without
examination, whatever sooths superstition, and promotes wonder.
How
many stories of this nature have, in all ages, been detected and exploded in
their infancy? How many more have been celebrated for a time, and have
afterwards sunk into neglect and oblivion? Where such reports, therefore, fly
about, the solution of the phenomenon is obvious; and we judge in conformity to
regular experience and observation, when we account for it by the known and
natural principles of credulity and delusion. And shall we, rather than have a
recourse to so natural a solution, allow of a miraculous violation of the most
established laws of nature?
I
need not mention the difficulty of detecting a falsehood in any private or even
public history, at the place, where it is said to happen; much more when the
scene is removed to ever so small a distance. Even a court of judicature, with
all the authority, accuracy, and judgement, which they can employ, find
themselves often at a loss to distinguish between truth and falsehood in the
most recent actions. But the matter never comes to any issue, if trusted to the
common method of altercations and debate and flying rumors; especially when
men's passions have taken part on either side.
In
the infancy of new religions, the wise and learned commonly esteem the matter
too inconsiderable to deserve their attention or regard. And when afterwards
they would willingly detect the cheat, in order to undeceive the deluded
multitude, the season is now past, and the records and witnesses, which might
clear up the matter, have perished beyond recovery.
No
means of detection remain, but those which must be drawn from the very
testimony itself of the reporters: and these, though always sufficient with the
judicious and knowing, are commonly too fine to fall under the comprehension of
the vulgar.
Upon
the whole, then, it appears, that no testimony for any kind of miracle has ever
amounted to a probability, much less to a proof; and that, even supposing it
amounted to a proof, it would be opposed by another proof; derived from the
very nature of the fact, which it would endeavor to establish. It is experience
only, which gives authority to human testimony; and it is the same experience,
which assures us of the laws of nature. When, therefore, these two kinds of
experience are contrary, we have nothing to do but subtract the one from the
other, and embrace an opinion, either on one side or the other, with that
assurance which arises from the remainder. But according to the principle here
explained, this subtraction, with regard to all popular religions, amounts to
an entire annihilation; and therefore we may establish it as a maxim, that no
human testimony can have such force as to prove a miracle, and make it a just
foundation for any such system of religion.
I
beg the limitations here made may be remarked, when I say, that a miracle can
never be proved, so as to be the foundation of a system of religion. For I own,
that otherwise, there may possibly be miracles, or violations of the usual
course of nature, of such a kind as to admit of proof from human testimony;
though, perhaps, it will be impossible to find any such in all the records of
history. Thus, suppose, all authors, in all languages, agree, that, from the
first of January 1600, there was a total darkness over the whole earth for
eight days: suppose that the tradition of this extraordinary event is still
strong and lively among the people: that all travelers, who return from foreign
countries, bring us accounts of the same tradition, without the least variation
or contradiction: it is evident, that our present philosophers, instead of
doubting the fact, ought to receive it as certain, and ought to search for the
causes whence it might be derived. The decay, corruption, and dissolution of
nature is an event rendered probable by so many analogies, that any phenomenon,
which seems to have a tendency towards that catastrophe, comes within the reach
of human testimony, if that testimony be very extensive and uniform.
But
suppose, that all the historians who treat of England, should agree, that, on
the first of January 1600, Queen Elizabeth died; that both before and after her
death she was seen by her physicians and the whole court, as is usual with
persons of her rank; that her successor was acknowledged and proclaimed by the
parliament; and that, after being interred a month, she again appeared, resumed
the throne, and governed England for three years: I must confess that I should
be surprised at the concurrence of so many odd circumstances, but should not
have the least inclination to believe so miraculous an event. I should not
doubt of her pretended death, and of those other public circumstances that
followed it: I should only assert it to have been pretended, and that it
neither was, nor possibly could be real. You would in vain object to me the
difficulty, and almost impossibility of deceiving the world in an affair of such
consequence; the wisdom and solid judgement of that renowned queen; with the
little or no advantage which she could reap from so poor an artifice: All this
might astonish me; but I would still reply, that the knavery and folly of men
are such common phenomena, that I should rather believe the most extraordinary
events to arise from their concurrence, than admit of so signal a violation of
the laws of nature.
But
should this miracle be ascribed to any new system of religion; men, in all
ages, have been so much imposed on by ridiculous stories of that kind, that
this very circumstance would be a full proof of a cheat, and sufficient, with
all men of sense, not only to make them reject the fact, but even reject it
without farther examination. Though the Being to whom the miracle is ascribed,
be, in this case, Almighty, it does not, upon that account, become a whit more
probable; since it is impossible for us to know the attributes or actions of
such a Being, otherwise than from the experience which we have of his
productions, in the usual course of nature. This still reduces us to past
observation, and obliges us to compare the instances of the violation of truth
in the testimony of men, with those of the violation of the laws of nature by
miracles, in order to judge which of them is most likely and probable. As the
violations of truth are more common in the testimony concerning religious
miracles, than in that concerning any other matter of fact; this must diminish
very much the authority of the former testimony, and make us form a general
resolution, never to lend any attention to it, with whatever specious pretense
it may be covered.
Lord
Bacon seems to have embraced the same principles of reasoning. 'We ought,' says
he, 'to make a collection or particular history of all monsters and prodigious
births or productions, and in a word of everything new, rare, and extraordinary
in nature. But this must be done with the most severe scrutiny, lest we depart
from truth. Above all, every relation must be considered as suspicious, which
depends in any degree upon religion, as the prodigies of Livy: And no less so, everything
that is to be found in the writers of natural magic or alchemy, or such
authors, who seem, all of them, to have an unconquerable appetite for falsehood
and fable.'
I
am the better pleased with the method of reasoning here delivered, as I think
it may serve to confound those dangerous friends or disguised enemies to
the Christian Religion, who have undertaken to defend it by the
principles of human reason. Our most holy religion is founded on Faith,
not on reason; and it is a sure method of exposing it to put it to such a trial
as it is, by no means, fitted to endure. To make this more evident, let us
examine those miracles, related in scripture; and not to lose ourselves in too
wide a field, let us confine ourselves to such as we find in the Pentateuch,
which we shall examine, according to the principles of these pretended
Christians, not as the word or testimony of God himself, but as the production
of a mere human writer and historian. Here then we are first to consider a
book, presented to us by a barbarous and ignorant people, written in an age
when they were still more barbarous, and in all probability long after the
facts which it relates, corroborated by no concurring testimony, and resembling
those fabulous accounts, which every nation gives of its origin. Upon reading
this book, we find it full of prodigies and miracles. It gives an account of a
state of the world and of human nature entirely different from the present: Of
our fall from that state: Of the age of man, extended to near a thousand years:
Of the destruction of the world by a deluge: Of the arbitrary choice of one
people, as the favorites of heaven; and that people the countrymen of the
author: Of their deliverance from bondage by prodigies the most astonishing
imaginable: I desire any one to lay his hand upon his heart, and after a
serious consideration declare, whether he thinks that the falsehood of such a
book, supported by such a testimony, would be more extraordinary and miraculous
than all the miracles it relates; which is, however, necessary to make it be
received, according to the measures of probability above established.
What we have said of miracles may be applied, without any
variation, to prophecies; and indeed, all prophecies are real miracles, and as
such only, can be admitted as proofs of any revelation. If it did not exceed
the capacity of human nature to foretell future events, it would be absurd to
employ any prophecy as an argument for a divine mission or authority from
heaven. So that, upon the whole, we may conclude, that the Christian
Religion not only was at first attended with miracles, but even at
this day cannot be believed by any reasonable person without one. Mere reason
is insufficient to convince us of its veracity: And whoever is moved by Faith to
assent to it, is conscious of a continued miracle in his own person, which
subverts all the principles of his understanding, and gives him a determination
to believe what is most contrary to custom and experience.
Additional Reading
For David Hume's Of Miracles, Part One, click here: https://www.finding-meaning-in-life.com/p/david-hume-of-miracles-part-one.html
If you enjoyed reading Of Miracles and want to read more on the subjects related to the essay, such as empiricism, skepticism, arguments for or against the existence of God, etc., click here to open a suggested reading list:
To read a brief introduction about David Hume and Of Miracles, click here: https://www.finding-meaning-in-life.com/p/introducing-david-humes-skeptical.html or you can return to the Finding Meaning in Life homepage here: https://www.finding-meaning-in-life.com/
No comments:
Post a Comment
Thank you for taking the time to read and comment on this blog!
Best regards,
Daniel D